Understandably, faced with very long prison sentences if convicted of murder, Professor Davison has concluded a court-approved plea and sentencing deal in pleading guilty to murder in respect of the three cases in which he assisted three persons in their death. For all three cases he received an eight year prison sentence wholly suspended, with three years conditional house arrest and community service. The Court took into account the compelling mitigating circumstances in the cases including Professor Davison’s compassionate motivation in seeking to assist those persons in a dignified death, that he was “remorseful for his actions”, and that each of those persons had requested the Professor for his assistance in dying and the relatives of each deceased were supportive of their and Professor Davison’s conduct.

It is interesting to compare the resolution of Professor Davison’s prosecutions with what at one time seemed to be the rather quaint outcome of the often referred to 1975 judgment in S v Hartmann1.

Hartmann was a medical practitioner practising in Ceres. His 87 year old father had been suffering for a number of years from a carcinoma of the prostrate and his condition had spread to other parts of his body with secondary cancer manifested in his bones and his ribs.

He had been treated elsewhere in the country but had come to Ceres for treatment as a private patient of his son at the local hospital. With no cure possible, Mr Hartmann senior’s treatment was symptomatic. By the time he was hospitalised in Ceres he was completely bedridden, extremely emaciated, incontinent and suffering great pain and treated through painkilling drugs. Mr Hartmann senior suffered a pulmonary embolus and laryngeal stridor, was treated and revived for a short time. He was, however, put on intravenous food because he could not swallow without choking. Within a short time, he was in a critical state, moribund, close to death, and suffering great pain which was treated through morphine administered via a drip.

The general picture of Mr Hartmann senior was of a patient in extreme misery due to bodily wasting and entirely dependent on his attendants for his simplest needs. The evidence presented strongly suggested that his quality of life had become meaningless. There was no dispute that Dr Hartmann was motivated in his actions solely by what he considered to be the best interests of his father.

Dr Hartmann had instructed a nursing sister to give his father half a gram of morphine which she had reluctantly done. An hour later Dr Hartmann himself administered a further half a gram of morphine through his father’s drip and about one and a half hours later injected 250 milligrams of pentothal into the drip. Within seconds Mr Hartmann senior died. The uncontroverted medical evidence was that the immediate cause of Mr Hartmann senior’s death was the administration of the pentothal.

The Court found that Dr Hartmann had not desired to end his father’s life but his motive had been compassionate to relieve his father of the further endurance of pain and a continuation of a pitiable condition. He was, however, aware that his conduct would inevitably terminate his father’s life.

Dr Hartmann was prosecuted and convicted of murder, the law being clear that the wilful hastening of the death of a human being who was due to die in any event constitutes the crime of murder. The evidence before the Court was that Mr Hartmann senior’s medical condition was so critical that he would in any event have died a few hours after Dr Hartmann administered the additional analgesics.

The Judge in considering a proper punishment said that the punishment must serve the public interest in the sense of discouraging a repetition of the offence by the offender and the prevention of like offences by others. The circumstance of the case was so unique that it could be accepted that the chances of the accused repeating his offence were negligible.

“In how far is there a deterrent necessary to prevent other medical men from taking similar action in respect to patients who are their close relatives or to their patients generally?”

In answering his own question, the Judge said: “Regard being had to the known commitment of the members of that profession to preserve life, I would think that such a deterrent has not a great role to play …This is a case, if ever there was one, in which, without having to be unfair to society, full measure can be given to the element of mercy.”

Dr Hartmann was sentenced to imprisonment for one year to be detained only until the rising of the Court with the balance of the sentence suspended for one year, subject to the condition that during that period Dr Hartmann was not to commit an offence involving the intentional infliction of bodily injury.

Dr Hartmann had the benefit of the then wording of the relevant section of the Criminal Procedure Act when it came to the penalty and the Court’s discretion.

Dr Hartmann, in any event, did not escape all sanction. He was charged before the South African Medical and Dental Council for unprofessional conduct and his name struck from the roll. He was after a lapse of time reinstated.

The matter was sympathetically reported in the press. At the time, however, no-one was prepared to propose any amendments to any laws to enable the lawful termination of a life in circumstances similar to those of Mr Hartmann senior.

Forty-four years later and there has been no real progress in developing our law on patient assisted euthanasia.

Professor Davison was responsible for ending the lives of three people between 2013 and 2015. He was not their doctor. He was the friend of one who had been rendered a quadriplegic in a car accident in 2015 and who had expressed his desire to die to Professor Davison. The Professor administered a lethal concoction of drugs to him. Another had asked the Professor to help him end his life after a stroke and being diagnosed with motor neuron disease which caused him difficulty in carrying out basic life tasks. Professor Davison placed a bag over his head and attempted to make use of helium deoxygenation. The third deceased was a young sportsman who had lost all motor function following a bicycle accident and who had communicated via eye movements his desire to die. Professor Davison administered a lethal dose of pentobarbital. On the information available it does not appear that any of those persons were in a final terminal stage comparable to that of Mr Hartmann senior.

Professor Davison’s reconsideration of his position was no doubt influenced not only by the enormous financial costs he was exposed to in litigating the three prosecutions, of course the severe penalties he faced if convicted following trial, but also the comments of, and less than enthusiastic approach of the Supreme Court of Appeal to develop the law of patient assisted euthanasia in the Stransham-Ford appeal.

The Supreme Court of Appeal in its 2016 judgment in the Stransham-Ford matter had to deal with a patient applicant suffering in the terminal stages of cancer. The patient had sought an order from the High Court permitting his medical practitioner to administer a lethal agent at his request or provide him with a lethal agent that he could administer himself. Mr Stransham-Ford died just before the High Court granted the order sought. The Court nevertheless declined to recall its order on the grounds that the judgment had broader societal implications.

The order of the lower court was taken on appeal to the Supreme Court of Appeal. The Supreme Court of appeal was clear that the nature of the relief claimed was a personal action and the purpose of the litigation was to obtain a court order to enable Mr Stransham-Ford to die in a manner of his own choosing. The Court said firmly that upon Mr Stransham-Ford’s death there was no longer an existing controversy, whether that involved Constitutional issues or not for the Court to pronounce upon and the case was no longer justiciable.

Because the relief sought was specifically tailored to Mr Stransham-Ford’s circumstances and only to any doctor who provided him with assistance to terminate his life, no public purpose was served by granting the order and it was not for the court to make orders on a cause of action that had been extinguished just because they thought their decisions would have broader societal implications. The court must wait for litigants to bring appropriate cases before them to develop a common law.

Referring with approval to a United States Supreme Court judgment the Court said :

“[Courts] do not, or should not, sally forth each day looking for wrongs to right.
We wait for cases to come to us, and when they do, we normally decide
only questions presented by the parties. Counsel almost always know a great deal more about their cases than we do … “

For that reason alone, the Supreme Court of Appeal set aside the lower court judgment.

It was then faced with the dilemma that there was a recent and reported judgment in the High Court dealing with, to some extent, the merits. The court went on to consider and explain why both on the law and on the facts the High Court should never have made the order it did in any event.

The court embarked on a review of the South African law regarding assisted suicide and the act of voluntary euthanasia and related issues and said that it is apparent that there are many steps available to both individuals facing the type of intolerable situations described and to the medical practitioners responsible for their care that will not result in interminable, purposeless treatment for the preservation of life as a purely mechanical process artificially maintained.

It was firm that “mercy killing” undoubtedly constitutes the crime of murder and referred to amongst others the judgment of Hartmann.

In commenting on whether the consent of the patient made any difference to the legal consequences of the medical practitioner’s conduct the court said that as the law stands it does not. Consent is not a defence available to the person who brings about the death of the deceased. Nor does the fact of consent justify a conviction on the lesser charge of culpable homicide.

The Supreme Court of Appeal firmly said that patient assisted euthanasia constitutes the crime of murder and a medical practitioner who administers a lethal agent to a patient at the latter’s request constitutes the crime of murder. If they did so the circumstances may materially affect the sentence imposed for that crime but the conviction would stand.

It noted that there were only four countries in the world that permitted patient assisted euthanasia and that if the common law were to be developed that needed to be confronted squarely and the scope and ambit of the requisite exception to, or departure from, the existing principles had to be defined.

That was not identified as an issue for consideration by the High Court and so it was not given full and proper consideration by the court. The Supreme Court of Appeal said an order making such a profound change to our law of murder, without any consideration of applicable principles, should not have been made.

The court distinguished patient assisted euthanasia (where the doctor administers a lethal substance to the patient) from patient assisted suicide (where the doctor provides the patient with an appropriate lethal agent which the patient themselves administers). Of course, it is not unlawful for the patient to have committed or attempted to commit suicide. The criminal exposure would attach to the medical practitioner who prescribed the means whereby the patient committed suicide.

In that regard our courts have found in previous matters before them on the facts that the person committing suicide had by their independent act in doing so been the cause of their own death even though the means for the cause of death had been supplied by another person, but commented that the voluntary and independent act of suicide need not always result in the acquittal of a another person accused of facilitating the suicide without reservation in regard to the independence of that act. While the immediate cause of the suicide’s death is the act of suicide that does not always necessarily interrupt the chain of causation between the conduct of the accused person and the person’s death so as to free the accused from criminal liability. Our courts recognise the possibility that a person may be guilty of murder if their actions were performed with criminal intent and there was no break in the chain of causation between their actions and the ultimate death of the suicide.

It will have to be determined on the facts of the particular case and of course the requirements of section 39 of our constitution which requires that in developing the common law our courts strive to give effect to the nature, purport and objects of the Bill of Rights. These are all things which were not considered by the lower court in the Stransham- Ford matter and there was no relevant evidence on the issues which the court would need to have considered in order to develop the common law.

The Supreme Court appeal judgment contains a very useful review of the law and different approaches of other jurisdictions regarding both patient assisted euthanasia and patient assisted suicide.

The Supreme Court of Appeal was very critical of the High Court saying that it:

  • misstated the situation in South African law;
  • failed to consider precisely what development was being sought;
  • treated patient assisted euthanasia and patient assisted suicide as clear and simple concepts capable of clear and simple application when they are nothing of the sought; and
  • did not recognise the distinction of the two;
  • paid little regard to international jurisprudence or to the answers to the Constitutional questions posed by the Supreme Court of Appeal;
  • claimed the relief it was granting was case dependent and not a precedent for a general “free for all” without any indication of how its effects could be limited;
  • erred in purporting to develop the common law of murder and culpable homicide in respect of an individual but not for the rest of society, when the factual record was inadequate particularly that relating to Mr Stransham-Ford’s physical condition and possible medical interventions;
  • did not give any consideration to what constraint on patient assisted euthanasia and patient assisted suicide would be reasonable and justifiable in an open and demographic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom;
  • was overly hasty to deal urgently with the matter so that insufficient opportunity was available for a fair public hearing and determination of the issues of the case. None of the relevant issues necessary to develop the common law was fully canvassed in the high court.

Project 86 of the South African Law Commission dealt with euthanasia and the artificial preservation of life and issued a report in November 1998.

The Commission did not make any specific recommendation regarding the act of voluntary euthanasia and set out various options.

One option was confirmation of the then, and now present, legal position that arguments in favour of legalising euthanasia are not sufficient reason to weaken societies prohibition of intentional killing since it is considered to be a cornerstone of our law and all social relationships. While there may be individual cases in which euthanasia may seem to be appropriate these cannot establish the foundation of a general pro-euthanasia policy.

The alternative option was to regulate the practice of active euthanasia through legislation in terms of which a medical practitioner may give effect to the request of a terminally ill but mentally competent patient to make an end to the patient’s unbearable suffering by the administration of providing a lethal agent to the patient. The medical practitioner would have to adhere to strict safeguards to prevent abuse. A further alternative suggested the practice of active euthanasia regulated through legislation in terms of which a multi- disciplinary panel or committee is instituted to consider requests for euthanasia according to set criteria.

Draft legislation in that regard was provided for consideration by Parliament.

Nothing of substance has happened since then.